Hasil (
Bahasa Indonesia) 1:
[Salinan]Disalin!
Akhirnya, dengan cara membersihkan tanah dan meletakkan dasar-dasar, sesuatu yang perlu dikatakan tentang sifat bahasa moral, dan dua cara yang saat ini modis mendekati moralitas harus diuraikan dan ditolak.Salah satu prestasi intuitionists adalah untuk mengingatkan kita bahwa penilaian moral khas atau sui generis. Sama seperti nilai-nilai tidak semua nilai-nilai moral, jadi tidak semua penilaian adalah penilaian moral. Tapi, lebih dari ini, penilaian moral seperti do 'That's salah' tidak bekerja dalam cara yang sama seperti, misalnya, estetika penilaian ('itu cantik'), perintah ('pergi'), penilaian mencicipi ('Aku memuja topi Anda'), atau, tentu saja, pernyataan-pernyataan tentang fakta empiris ('mobil itu terjadi pada 75 mph'). Filsuf abad kedua puluh membuat kontribusi tertentu kepada pemahaman kita sifat wacana moral-bagaimana moral fungsi ucapan-ucapan atau kerja-yang memberitahu kita sesuatu tentang sifat penilaian moral.Pertama (dalam sejarah istilah), disarankan bahwa ucapan-ucapan moral, meskipun tampak oleh bentuk mereka untuk membuat pernyataan setara dengan pernyataan deskriptif, bahkan yang secara harfiah berarti bahwa mereka tidak lebih dari outpourings emosi, kadang-kadang terlihat seperti yang dirancang untuk mempengaruhi orang lain, tapi kadang-kadang dilihat sebagai setara verbal memancarkan mendesah atau teriakan sukacita. Dengan demikian, 'Pencurian salah' tidak dilihat sebagai membuat pernyataan tentang mencuri, sebanding dengan mengatakan 'mobil cokelat'; Hal ini terlihat sebagai cara yang tidak lebih dan tidak kurang dari lain pergi 'mencuri – ugh!', dengan atau tanpa harapan memimpin orang lain untuk berbagi atau evince ketidaksukaan sama.This theory, as baldly stated, did not survive for long and did not deserve to do so. In the first place, it is not always the case that I am trying to influence others and it is arguable that it is not always even a form of self-expression. When I lie awake musing on the wrongdoing in the world, saying to myself, ‘All this stealing is wrong, but I’m not sure whether speaking bluntly is wrong’, I am certainly not seeking to influence anybody and I am not obviously giving vent to my disgust or enthusiasm. In the second place, this desire to influence or express oneself does not distinguish a moral utterance from many other kinds of utterance or activity such as advertising, political speeches, threats, and propaganda. But if one thing is clear it is that a moral utterance such as ‘Kindness is good’ cannot be equated with remarks of the type ‘Do this or else’, or with a shriek of joy celebrating Coca-Cola. It is true that it is part of the nature of (much?) moral discourse to evince our own attitudes and to attempt to influence those of others, and that is an important insight, but it is not by any means all that moral discourse does. If it were, then the criteria for a successful moral argument would be purely and simply the ability to get others to accept one’s view or relative success in expressing one’s passion. But this is not what constitutes a good moral argument. A moral debate is not to be compared with an Oscar night; it is not a popularity contest.But there are other truths about moral utterances that derive not from contemplation of what we are trying to achieve by making them, but rather from what is involved in making them. Two of these truths are that moral language is prescriptive and universalizable. It is prescriptive inasmuch as moral utterances, whatever their grammatical form, may be seen as disguised imperatives. To understand and accept that ‘I ought to pay back the money I borrowed’ is to see the force of the command, ‘Repay what you borrow’. One is logically committed not just to saying that one agrees that one should, but to the act of repayment. By your deeds shall ye be known. If you don’t repay your debts, then (other things being equal, e.g. if you don’t have a gun held to your head) you don’t sincerely have that moral viewpoint; you don’t truly recognize that you should repay debts, whatever you may say. But not only is moral language prescriptive, its implicit imperatives, unlike everyday imperatives such as ‘Shut the door’, carry with them implications for other similar occasions and for other people. The fact that I command you to shut the door implies nothing about whether I shall command or expect you to close it tomorrow or about whether I shall expect others to close it. There is nothing illogical about saying ‘Shut the door’ to one friend and not to another. But that is not true of a moral command, however it is phrased. Whether explicit (‘You ought to be kind’) or implicit (‘Kindness is good’), it is logically implied both that we should all be kind and that we should always be kind (other things being equal). One way of summarizing this point is to say that moral utterances are, by their nature, universalizable. If I say or believe that my neighbour should not play his trumpet after midnight, then I should not play my trombone after midnight either; and if I say that consideration is a moral good, then I should be expected both to show consideration and to demand it from others.
Sedang diterjemahkan, harap tunggu..
